Does Enslaving Others Help the Economy or Not?
Robert E. Wright, Nef Family Chair of Political Economy, Augustana University, for the Historians Against Slavery Symposium, Loyola University, New Orleans, La., 19 February 2016.
For millennia,
the answer to the query posed in the title of this talk would have been “of course slavery helps the economy.” Even
early abolitionists believed that
slavery was an economic “necessity,”
so they concentrated on the many immoral
aspects of the institution. These early views were premised on the well-supported
belief that enslaving others was profitable
for enslavers. Surely some enslavers owned too many slaves or otherwise
botched the management of their households or commercial enterprises but no economic institution of such ubiquity
and longevity could have been unprofitable on average. Slavery of course
began in prehistory and touched every major society on every inhabited continent.
In the eighteenth century, Benjamin Franklin, Adam Smith, and others argued strenuously that slavery was unprofitable because slaves did not have much incentive to
work hard or smart. Enslavers and abolitionists alike knew claims of unprofitability were wrong, so
their arguments, eloquent as they
were, fell flat.
In the nineteenth century, by contrast,
U.S. observers like Cassius Marcellus Clay,
Hinton Rowan Helper, and Frederick Law Olmsted noted that slave districts did not keep pace economically with regions relatively devoid of slaves.
Real per capita incomes were lower in
the slave states, which also lagged the
so-called free states in education,
infrastructure, and other measures of development,
i.e., the capacity to generate growth. All three authors blamed slavery for the discrepancy. It was not that slavery was unprofitable for slaveholders, they
argued, it was that profitability did
not ensure economic growth or development. During the Civil War, Irish
economist John Elliott Cairnes made
the matter clear:
Those
who are acquainted with the elementary principles which govern the distribution
of wealth, know that the profits of capitalists may be increased by the same
process by which the gross revenue of a country is diminished, and that
therefore the community as a whole may be impoverished through the very same
means by which a portion of its number is enriched. The economic success of
slavery, therefore, is perfectly consistent with the supposition that it is
prejudicial to the material well-being of the country where it is established.
That slavery led to enslaver
profit but economic backwardness became the standard interpretation, as in Lewis C. Gray’s History of
Agriculture in the Southern United States to 1860, save of course in the racist literature inspired by Ulrich
Bonnell Phillips, which argued that
slavery was too paternalist to be profitable.
Stan Engerman and Bob Fogel put that notion to bed in Time on the Cross and Without Consent or Contract. Subsequent
studies, like John Majewski’s A House Dividing, documented the South’s
relative economic backwardness
without challenging slavery’s
profitability for individual enslavers or even its economic efficiency, narrowly defined.
Recently, however, a bevy of books by Ed Baptist, Calvin Schermerhorn, Robin
Blackburn and others have claimed that slavery
was an indispensable part of the Industrial
Revolution, the development of
capitalism, and so forth. In their view, slavery was both profitable and crucial
for economic growth and development.
These good folks are trying to lay the grounds for reparations but at the
same time putting living people at increased
risk of enslavement by providing
developing world officials with yet another reason not to clamp down on human
trafficking, debt peonage, child soldiering, and so forth. If slavery made the U.S. wealthy, as Baptist and his buddies claim, such officials reason, then aren’t antislavery efforts just another imperialist attempt to keep their
nations impoverished? Perhaps slavery should even be encouraged. Maybe slavery is immoral,
they reason, but the ends justify the
means.
I believe that Baptist et al are wrong and Helper
et al were right. For starters, slavery can’t be a necessary cause of growth because the Dutch became wealthy before
they began enslaving others and the Scandinavians after they gave it up. It
also can’t be a sufficient cause of
growth because most slave societies did not experience sustained economic
growth or development. The best that
can be said of slavery is that it did not completely
stop the growth or development of some economies, like that of the
antebellum U.S. South.
But let me be clear that slavery did not help the overall U.S. economy. In fact, I’m sure that enslaving others always hurts the overall economy regardless of how
profitable it is for individual
enslavers or how efficient it is in narrow economic terms. That is because slavery
creates very large negative
externalities, or costs imposed
on society rather than on enslavers. Slavery, in other words, is akin to pollution spewing from an
unregulated factory. The factory owners
get rich and the factory appears to
be very efficient because it
produces goods at a relatively low cost, but only because the people downwind and downstream of the factory pay the bulk of the costs in the form of dirty
and poisonous air and water.
The negative
externalities created by slavery are, unfortunately, more difficult to see than smoke plumes and dead fish but they did,
and do, exist. They range from the socialized
costs of controlling slaves by means of slave patrols, fugitive
slave acts, public whipping posts,
and insurrections to the opportunity cost of slaves’ lost talents.
Other factors equal, slaves die younger
than free people and are more likely to spread
disease and suffer from debilitating
accidents and psychological
disorders. They are much less likely
to be literate or to invent new
tools or techniques. In short, masters
deprive society of their slaves’ full human potential. Thomas Fuller, for example, did drudge work at
his masters bidding instead of mathematics
although he could solve complex arithmetic problems in his head faster than any
of his educated, white challengers could do using pen and paper. From society’s
standpoint, Fuller should have been
a merchant or a census enumerator, not part of a potent military threat.
The problem
with all of the recent studies
that purport to show that slavery helped the U.S. economy is that they ignore the numerous negative externalities created by slavery.
In other words, they forgot the lesson of Bastiat’s
Window, or “That Which is Seen, and That Which is Not Seen.” In that
parable by French political economist Frederic Bastiat, a boy breaks a shopkeeper’s window. Onlookers beseech the
shopkeeper not to be angry with the boy because he has provided employment for
a window maker. Bastiat grants that fact but notes “All this is that which is seen.” That which is unseen, Bastiat
points out, is that due to the broken window the shopkeeper has less money with which
to buy bread, wine, cheese, and so forth. So the boy’s actions did not help to stimulate the economy,
as the onlookers suggested, but merely redistributed
wealth from the bread maker to the window maker. Plus, the little bastard broke a window.
In Bastiat’s
language, the profits of slavery are
that which is seen. That which is not
seen are the negative externalities caused by slavery, the death,
destruction, and rapine that always accompanies the enslavement of others and
that imposes significant costs onto society at large, i.e., the overall economy. In Baptist’s language, negative
externalities are yet another half
untold.
Measuring
all the many negative externalities
created by slavery with any degree of precision is difficult if not impossible but thankfully we do not need a close accounting to be convinced
that they outweigh the benefits of
slavery, which of course are only marginal.
In other words, to discern the effects of slavery on the overall economy we
should not compare the negative externalities to profits but only to those
profits due to the use of enslaved labor, or, in other words, the enslavers’ profits minus the profits
that he/she or it would have earned without the use of slaves. That is also
difficult to measure precisely but we know
it is usually relatively small, on the order of a few percent of total
profits at most.
While developing this argument, it
became clear to me that we should not maintain binary definitions of slave and free. Julia O’Connell Davidson’s Modern Slavery: The Margins of Freedom
cemented that conclusion for me. I have therefore created a scale of freedom that ranges from 0 to
20 based on 20 questions about a given worker’s ability to make decisions for
him or herself. Chattel slaves in a gang system score 0 on my freedom scale and today’s
CEOs 20. Modern debt peons in
India score a 3 or 4. Wage laborers in the antebellum North
score about a 10, while wage laborers in the U.S. today
generally score around a 15. The higher the score, the smaller the negative
externalities that are created. So public policy should encourage increasing every worker’s freedom by
as much as possible, starting, of
course, with those with the lowest
freedom scores, who we term modern slaves.
When I had lunch with Kevin Bales back in September, he responded enthusiastically to the notion of a scale of freedom but I have not
yet heard back from him on the
details. With your permission,
I’d like to read the questions,
which I have divided into three sections,
direct methods of control, working conditions, and personal life, to you for your comments. You might think of
your own work situation as I go through these. Yes answers get a 1, no a 0, sometimes or it depends a .5.
Keep in mind throughout that these
questions relate directly to the employer-employee
relationship and not to all
constraints that workers face. A laborer confined to a wheelchair due to polio, for example, is not physically restrained by his or her employer but rather by reality. Similarly, workers who are
allowed to seek, but cannot find, other
employment are constrained by economic conditions, not by their
respective employers.
Direct Methods of
Control:
1. Is
the laborer paid primarily in cash
or other liquid asset (e.g., company stock)?
2. Can
the laborer own property on the same
terms as his or her employer?
3. Is
the laborer free from physical
restraints?
4. Is
the laborer free from psychological
constraints?
5. Is
the laborer not legally required to work?
6. Is
the laborer inalienable (unsalable
or otherwise nontransferable to another employer without his or her consent)?
7. Is
the laborer incapable of owing his/her
employer significant sums or of being listed as collateral security for an
advance or other loan payable to his/her employer?
8. Has
the worker not been subjected to
“seasoning” designed to break his/her will to find other employment?
9. Does
the laborer have freedom of movement
in order to search for other employment?
10. Can
the laborer quit without monetary or
other loss?
Working
Conditions:
11. Can
the laborer control his/her work
schedule?
12. Can
the laborer control the total hours s/he
works?
13. Can
the laborer control the tempo of his or
her work?
Personal
Life:
14. Is
the laborer not legally “dead,”
“socially dead,” or otherwise alienated from the formal or dominant social
order?
15. Does
the laborer not belong to a group
that has been “dishonored?”
16. Can
the laborer determine his/her own name?
17. Can
the laborer determine what to consume
and where to buy consumption goods?
18. Can
the laborer choose his/her place of residence?
19. Is
the laborer able to marry on the
same terms as his or her employer?
20. Does
the laborer control his or her own
children on the same terms as his or her employer?
Again, the argument is that less worker freedom means more negative
externalities which means less growth
and development. The effect is most
pronounced with slaves but any increase in freedom for any worker
should have beneficial effects on
the overall economy. Any questions or observations on any of this?
No comments:
Post a Comment